Characterizing properties of stochastic objective ... - Semantic Scholar

Report 6 Downloads 141 Views
MIT LIBRARIES

3 9080 03130 2398 | HB31 .M415

working paper department of economics

CHARACTERIZING PROPERTIES OF STOCHASTIC OBJECTIVE FUNCTIONS Susan Athey 96-1

Oct. 1995

massachusetts institute of

technology 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass. 02139

CHARACTERIZING PROPERTIES OF STOCHASTIC OBJECTIVE FUNCTIONS Susan Athey 96-1

Oct. 1995

INTRODUCTION

1

This paper studies optimization problems where the objective function can be written in the form

V(8)

=

\jt{s)dF{s\6),

payoff function,

;ris a

For example, the payoff function

real vectors.

the vector s

where

F

is

a probability distribution, and 6 and s are

n might represent

might represent features of the current

state

an agent's

utility

or a firm's profits,

of the world, and the elements of 6 might

represent an agent's investments, effort decisions, other agent's choices, or the nature of the

exogenous uncertainty in the agent's environment.

The economic problem under consideration often determines some properties of function; for example, a utility

the payoff

function might be assumed to be nondecreasing and concave, while a

multivariate profit function might have sign restrictions on cross-partial derivatives.

assumptions then determine a set questions such as:

investments? questions,

Is

IT

a set of investments 6

Does one investment increase

we need

know whether

to

is

These

We might then wish to answer

of admissible payoff functions.

worthwhile? Are there decreasing returns to those

the returns to another investment?

V(Q) satisfies the appropriate properties,

To answer

i.e.,

those

nondecreasing,

concave, or supermodular. 1

The goal of

paper

this

is to

develop methods such

nondecreasing), a set of admissible payoff functions

we can J

determine whether the following statement

7i(s)dF(s; 6) satisfies property

That

is,

given

P

and

II,

II,

that,

given a particular property

(1.1)

describe the set of probability distributions which satisfy (1.1).

This paper restricts attention to the case where the properties cones."

which

P

and

sets II are "closed

convex

We define a property P to be a "Closed Convex Cone" (CCC) property if the set of functions

satisfy

P is closed (under an appropriate topology), positive combinations of functions in the set

are also in the set,

and constant functions are

in the set. Important

nondecreasing, concave, supermodular, any property which

is

examples of CCC properties include

defined by placing a sign restriction on

a partial derivative, and combinations of these properties. Thus,

consumer's

1

(such as

is true:

P in 6 for all n in IL

we wish to

P

and a parameterized probability distribution F,

utility, II

Intuitively, a function is

to increasing the other.

if

the payoff function represents a

could be the set of univariate, nondecreasing, concave payoff functions;

supermodular

When

if.

if the

given any two arguments of the function, increasing one increases the returns

the function

is differentiable, this

amounts to positive cross-partial derivatives between

every pair of arguments. Supermodularity is important in the context of comparative statics (see Topkis (1978), Milgrom and Roberts (1990, 1994), Milgrom and Shannon (1994)).

payoff function represents a firm's profits as a function of two complementary quality innovations,

n

could be the set of bivariate, nondecreasing, supermodular payoff functions.

For

sets II

P

and for properties

which

probability distributions satisfy (1.1).

be a very large

set.

Thus we

ask,

are

CCC,

Checking

When is

it

this

paper develops a characterization of which

(1.1) directly is difficult because, in general, If

might

possible to find a smaller set of payoff functions, denoted

T, so that for any probability distribution F, statement (1.2)

below

will

be true

if

and only

if (1.1) is

true?

7t(s)dF(s;8) satisfies property J

P in 6 for all % in T

We can think of T as a "test set" easier to check than II, but

only the information that

Using these

ideas,

it

P is

T

is

a set of payoff functions which

whether

test

J

is

7C(s)dF(s;0) satisfies property

.2)

smaller and

P in

6,

given

K is in the larger set II.

we can restate the goal

the best "test set" for a given II.

property

for II: ideally,

can be used to

( 1

We

of the paper:

proceed in two

"nondecreasing"; second,

we

study other

we want

steps.

a theory which helps us determine

First,

we examine

CCC properties.

The

the case

first

where the

case has been the

focus of the literature on stochastic dominance, where different authors have studied different sets

II. 2

This paper unifies and extends the existing literature on stochastic dominance, providing an exact characterization of the mathematical structure underlying all stochastic further provide an algorithm for generating

hoc

differentiability

part of the paper

when V{6)

we show

that the

We now provide

stochastic

an overview of our is

results.

We

dominance theorems which relaxes the ad

common

in this literature. 3 In the

methods from stochastic dominance can be applied

satisfies other properties P, including

property nondecreasing, if II is

new

and continuity assumptions which are

dominance theorems.

second

to characterize

concavity and supermodularity. In the first part of this paper,

we show

that for the

a closed convex cone and contains constant functions, then the best

T

the set of "extreme points" of II. Just as a basis generates a linear space via linear combinations, so

a set of extreme points generates a closed convex cone via positive linear combinations and limits.

Thus,

want

2

we show that if we know only that a payoff function k lies in the closed convex cone II, and we know if V(6) is nondecreasing, it is equivalent to check that V(0) is nondecreasing on a smaller

to

In particular, the univariate stochastic dominance problem has been studied by Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970, 1971) and Hadar and Russell (1971); notable contributions to the multivariate problem include Levy and Paroush (1974), Atkinson and Bourguignon (1982), and Meyer (1990). Shaked and Shanthikumar (1994) provide a reference book on the subject of stochastic orders and their applications in economics, biology, and statistics. 3 Brumelle and Vickson (1975) take a first step towards relaxing these assumptions and identifying the mathematical structure behind stochastic dominance; in contrast to their work, which provides only sufficient conditions for a stochastic dominance relationship, this paper provides an exact characterization of all stochastic dominance theorems.

set

of payoff functions, the extreme points of n.

V(6) for the set of extreme points of

extreme points of

n

n

It

than for

will often

n

be much easier to verify monotonicity of

In this paper, the procedure of using the

itself.

as a test set for II will be referred to as the "closed

convex cone" method of

proving stochastic dominance theorems.

Examples from the existing include First Order Stochastic

dominance

stochastic

which are special cases of this

literature,

Dominance (FOSD), where

n is the

set

of univariate, nondecreasing

payoff functions, and Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD), where TI

concave payoff functions.

In the case of

functions which are zero up to the case of 2,

SOSD,

some

the set of extreme

FOSD,

result,

the set of univariate,

is

the set of extreme points is the set of one-step

constant, and one thereafter.

points is the set

These are pictured

in Figure

1

.

In

of "angle," or "min" functions, pictured in Figure

where each function takes the minimum of its argument and some constant.

The closed convex cone method

for stochastic

dominance has been recognized and explored

in the

context of particular sets of payoff functions (Topkis, 1968; Brumelle and Vickson, 1974; Gollier and

Kimball, 1995). 4 However, this paper goes beyond the existing literature in two respects.

developing appropriate abstract definitions to describe stochastic dominance theorems,

make

we are

by

able to

general statements about the entire class of stochastic dominance theorems, including those

which have not yet been considered that

First,

we prove

a

new

in the

cone" approach to stochastic dominance return the

same answer

and (1.2) equivalent. In

is

if

we prove

exactly the right one.

these are not in T)

is

shows

characterize other properties of V(6).

that the "closed

the fact

By this we mean that (1.1) and

IT;

no other T's

which generates

(1.2)

will always

make

(1.1)

II is the best set to check.

convex cone" method can also be applied

to

We ask two questions: First, for what properties P is the closed

convex cone approach valid? And second, for what properties

P is

exactly the right one, as in the case of stochastic dominance? property, then the closed

is

formally that the "closed convex

F if and only if the closed convex cone of T

equal to

this case, clearly the smallest set

part of this paper

Second and more important

literature.

for every probability distribution

(union the constant functions,

The second

economics

result about this class of theorems:

the closed

We

first

convex cone approach

show

that if

P

is

convex cone approach can always be used to characterize when V(6)

a

CCC

satisfies

We then find a subset of CCC properties, which we call "Linear Difference Properties," for which we can show that the closed convex cone approach is exactly the right one for checking whether V(0)

P.

satisfies P.

Examples of Linear Difference Properties include monotonicity, supermodularity,

concavity, and properties which place sign restrictions

on

partial derivatives.

Combinations of these

properties, however, are not in general Linear Difference Properties, although such combinations are

4Independently, Gollier and Kimball (1995) argue for what they

4

call the "basis

approach" to stochastic dominance.

I

CCC

properties.

Table

I

summarizes properties which are

CCC

properties and Linear Difference

Properties.

TABLE LINEAR DIFFERENCE PROPERTIES AND CLOSED CONVEX CONE PROPERTIES Property

Closed Convex Cone

Linear Difference Property

Nondecreasing

Yes

Yes

Supermodular

Yes

Yes

Concave/Convex (Multivariate)

Yes

Yes

Sign Restriction on a Partial

Yes

Yes

Constant

Yes

No

Nondecreasing and Concave

Yes

No

Arbitrary Combinations of

Yes

No

Yes

No

Derivative

CCC Properties Arbitrary Combinations of

LDP

Properties

For many literature

cases, the

on

sets

of payoff functions, n, which are

stochastic

dominance has

commonly

studied in economics, the existing

implicitly identified the extreme points of those sets. In such

problem of characterizing a Linear Difference Property (such as supermodularity) becomes

quite straightforward: simply look to the the existing literature to find the appropriate test set, T, for the set

of payoff functions II under consideration. Then, using the results of this paper,

(1.2) characterizes the set

function will be supermodular for

We

illustrate this

we know

that

of parameterized probability distributions for which the stochastic objective all

payoff functions in

technique by showing

how

II.

the closed convex cone approach can be used to

characterize the property supermodularity for several important classes of payoff functions. These results

can in turn provide sufficient (and sometimes necessary) conditions for comparative

conclusions. In particular,

we examine

statics

applications in principal-agent theory, welfare economics, and

the study of coordination problems in firms.

This paper proceeds as follows.

In Section 2,

we

introduce a motivating example, the problem of

a risk- averse agent's choice of effort. In this problem,

concave, and supermodular for the agent's expected

dominance takes place

in Section 3.

We provide

we characterize

utility function.

the properties nondecreasing,

Our general

an exact characterization of stochastic dominance

We further extend our

theorems, highlighting the important role played by linearity of the integral. result to incorporate "conditional stochastic

properties of

we

dominance." Section 4 develops characterizations of other

7t(s)dF(s;d) and provides applications of the property supermodularity. In Section 5, f

K(x,s)dF(s;6) are supermodular or

analyze conditions under which functions of the form

concave

analysis of stochastic

in (x,d),

showing how

J

to apply stochastic monotonicity results to this

problem

as well.

Section 6 concludes.

2

MOTIVATING EXAMPLE:

A RISK-AVERSE AGENT'S CHOICE OF EFFORT In this section,

we present

a motivating example, where

how

of effort affects her expected payoffs, and

we

analyze

Formally,

nondecreasing, concave, and supermodular for the agent's expected

examples

stochastic



examples where the payoff function

is

illustrate the parallel structure

Consider a risk-averse agent whose technology, where the output

is

denoted

s.

Suppose t

utility function.

another. Then,

t

we can write the agent's problem as max

observe that

it is

not

an increase in effort which

results are

nondecreasing and concave



of a

is

underlying the three classes of theorems.

that the agent's effort (c) affects the probability

k(s) dF(s; e,t)-c(e) •

f

=

\it(s) dF(s;e,t) is

some

-

c(e) is

= ae such

that the

FOCs

effort:

utility if the effort also

concave is

in effort, then

useful in the analysis

as principal agent problems. Further, if V(e,i) fails to

linear cost function c(e)

optimum. Finally, observe

nondecreasing in

productive on average might not increase expected

order conditions (FOCs) characterize the optimum, a property which

then there exists

to

follows:

trivial to verify that V(e,t)

some economic problems, such

in the stochastic

might represent a worker moving from one job

increases the riskiness of the distribution. Second, note that if V(e,t)

e,

These

which represents exogenous changes

production technology. For example, a change in

first

exogenous

characterize the properties

depends on the output of a stochastic production

utility {it)

distribution of s. Further, consider a parameter

the

we

dominance theorem, a "stochastic concavity theorem," and a "stochastic supermodularity

theorem." These examples

First

a risk-averse agent's choice

that choice of effort interacts with

parameters which describe the probability distribution.

specific

how

fail to

be concave

in

characterize the

that if V{e,i) is supermodular, then the optimal choice of effort, e*(t), is

nondecreasing in

If V(e,t) fails to

t.

linear cost function c(e)

=

ae

Milgrom and Shannon (1994); satisfies the

be supermodular, then even

such that e*{i)

fails to

Theorem A.l

see

in the

cannot be relaxed as long as

it

V is

concave, there exists some t

follows from

(this

Appendix). Thus, the requirement that

property supermodular (or concave, respectively)

conclusion, and further

if

be nondecreasing in

we

is

sufficient for the desired

V(e,t)

economic

require that the conclusion holds for

all

linear cost functions.

Let us

first

identify conditions under

known

result is adapted

(where

we suppress

Proposition 2.1

t

which

from the Rothschild and

nondecreasing in

V(e,i) is

Stiglitz (1970,

e.

The following

well-

1971) work on stochastic dominance

in the notation):

The following two conditions are equivalent for

all probability distributions

F(-,e): (i)

For all K nondecreasing and concave, The following are

(ii)

dF(s;e)

is

nondecreasing in

e.

satisfied:

\sdF(s;e)

(a)

\lt(s)

is

nondecreasing

in

e.

a

For all a, -\F(s;e)

(b)

Intuitively, for a risk-averse agent

mean income

effort increases the

This result

is

is

nondecreasing

who likes income,

(condition

(ii)(a))

often used in the finance literature;

it

in e.

effort will increase

expected

utility if

and only

and reduces the "risk function" (condition

if

(ii)(b)).

has been called Second Order Monotonic Stochastic

Dominance (SOMSD).

we

In this paper,

conditions

(i)

and

(ii)

will

A

1

Proposition 2.1 (where

extended real

Proposition (i)

For

all

nondecreasing (ii)

in e.

u {-00

,

the set Yl

which emphasizes

The following proposition SR,

is

that

equivalent to

and Si indicates the

00 }):

The following two conditions are equivalent for

n in

2.1,

be the space of probability distributions defined on

line, that is, SR

2.1'

work with a restatement of Proposition

are actually symmetric conditions.

SOM

= [ti\k

:

SR



all

F(-;e)eN:

% nondecreasing, concave},

J

7t(s)

dF(s;e)

is

in e.

For all yin

the set

T SOM = {y\y(s) = min(a,s), a e 9t},

jy(s) dF(s\e)

is

nondecreasing

.

Conditions

(i)

and

(ii)

we have

except that

of this Proposition simply restate conditions

straightforward to verify (using integration by parts) that the former term if

the latter term

This condition

is.

(1975) for an exception).

This

way of

structure underlying the stochastic that instead of

relatively large set, II

50M ,

sets of

the union of

is

set,

T

is itself

relationship

y{s)

Now,

a closed convex cone.

between

let

Tl

and

r

nondecreasing

=

and

1

is

illustrates the 1',

mathematical the result says

for all payoff functions in the

X

is

nondecreasing in e for

all

SOM

all

=

between the two

of

relationship

That

-1.

latter set,

In Section 3,

holds for

The

2.

we

we can

will

stochastic

is,

show

by taking

to analyzing principal-agent

generate any function in TI SOM , that this "closed

convex cone"

dominance theorems.

When is

problems

are satisfied, then the agent's choice of effort

sets

positive combinations

J

x(s) dF(s;e) concave in effort? This

problem was addressed by Jewitt (1988), who analyzes conditions under which the

FOCs

and only

equal to the closed convex cone of the set which

y(s)

us ask a different, but related, question:

Approach (FOA)

if

is

It

.

and the functions

SOM

is

(ii).

2.1,

S0M

and limits of sequences (or nets) of elements of the

which

of Proposition

in Proposition 2.

nondecreasing in

payoff functions are pictured in Figure

T S0M

theorem

dominance theorem. As written

S0M payoff functions can be described as follows: T1 is

SOMSD

equivalent to check that \y(s)dF(s;e)

it is

payoff functions in the smaller

The two

writing the

checking that j n(s) dF(s;e)

(ii)

SOMSD (see Brumelle and Vickson

not usually associated with

is

and

jmin(a,s)dF(s;e) in condition

with

replaced -JF(s;e)

(i)

is valid.

The

First

Order

FOA requires that if the agent's

must be optimal. Extending

Jewitt' s analysis,

we

can show that the sufficient conditions he derives are in fact necessary. 5 The following result analogous to Proposition

Proposition 2.2 (i)

(ii)

For

The following two conditions are equivalent for

all

For

all

% in

is

2.1:

the set Yl

yin the set

S0M

\k(s) dF(s;e)

is

concave

in e.

y(s) dF(s;e)

is

concave

in



,

T SOM

all

',

\

F(;e)e A

1

:

e.

Proof: This will be established as a simple corollary of Theorem 4. 1 below, together with Proposition 2. 1

Q.E.D.

5 Jewitt first derives conditions under which the agent's utility function is increasing and concave in output, given the optimal contract; he then addresses the question of concavity of the expected utility function in effort. It is only the latter question which we study here.

Proposition 2.2 says that expected payoffs are concave in e for

only

expected payoffs are concave in e for

if

useful because condition

Condition

(

n

SOM ,

T

SOM

T SOM

payoff functions in

easier to check that condition

(ii) is

(i):

U SOM

payoff functions in .

the set

Again,

r

SOM

this

much

is

if

and

theorem

is

smaller.

can be interpreted as requiring that there are decreasing returns to e in terms of

(ii)

increasing the

all

all

mean and

), is

the

decreasing the "risk function." Note that the pair of sets of payoff functions,

same

in

both propositions.

Now we turn to ask a final question: When is the optimal choice of effort monotone nondecreasing in

t,

which parameterizes the stochastic production technology? More

way

probability distribution over output in such a

that

precisely,

how can

t

affect the

monotonicity of the optimal effort in

is

t

ensured, without any additional information about the cost of effort function or the agent's preferences?

This question has not been answered in the existing literature; thus, the following

proposition provides a

new

Proposition 2.3

monotone

cost functions c

and all K in

Il

SOM ,

e'(t)

all F(-;e,f)e

S0M

in

(i)

For all n e

(ii)

For all ye T S0M jy(s)

Tl

,

t.

is

supermodular

:

is

Js

in {e,t\

dF(s;e,t) is supermodular in

Proof: The equivalence of parts (1994), as stated in

1

6

\K{s)dF{s;e,t)

,

A

= argmax\K(s)dF(s;e,t)-c(t) e

monotone nondecreasing

that this proposition is

in effort.

The following three conditions are equivalent for

(MCS) For all

Note

insight into the comparative statics problem.

true irrespective of whether expected utility is

Theorem A. 1

(MCS) and in the

(i)

(e,t).

follows directly from

Milgrom and Shannon

Appendix. The equivalence of (i) and

established as a corollary of Theorem 4.1

below together with Proposition

(ii)

will

be

2.1.

Q.E.D.

The formal

definition of supermodularity (and the comparative statics

can be found in the Appendix. Intuitively,

V(e,t) is

supermodular

Proposition 2.3 provides necessary and sufficient conditions for

problem. If

(ii) is

choice of effort

is

violated, then

not monotonic in

monotone comparative increasing the

we

statics.

mean of the

if t

theorem which

relies

statics in this

can construct payoff functions and cost functions such that the t.

Thus,

Condition

we have

(ii)

identified the exact conditions

requires that e and

t

are

which ensure

complementary

probability distribution and in terms of reducing the risk.

may be a

Order, as defined in the Appendix.

set.

it)

increases the returns to effort.

monotone comparative

Then,

this

theorem requires

that the set

be nondecreasing

in terms of

The

straightforward: since a risk-averse, income-loving agent likes high expected returns and

"In general, the optimal e

upon

intuition is

low

risk (as

in the Strong Set

shown

SOMSD),

in

complementary

are

variables

which

in increasing

complementary

are

expected

utility

in increasing the

mean and

of such an agent. Note that

decreasing the risk

one of e and

if either

/

does not affect the mean or the riskiness of the agent's income, the corresponding complementarity conditions are satisfied trivially.

Notice that Propositions 2.2 and 2.3 have a structure which

dominance

stochastic

result, as stated in

analyzing Proposition 2.1

very similar to the existing

is

Proposition 2.1. In Section 3,

we

will build a

and other stochastic dominance theorems. In Section

we

4,

framework

for

will formalize

the relationship between Propositions 2.1 through 2.3.

MONOTONICITY OF STOCHASTIC OBJECTIVE FUNCTIONS

3

The goal of theorems.

dominance

two

sets

this section is to

provide a unified framework for analyzing stochastic dominance

we

introduce a framework which incorporates the existing stochastic

In Section 3.1, literature,

arguing that each stochastic dominance theorem describes a relationship between

we prove

of payoff functions. In Section 3.2,

relationship

between two

the stochastic

sets

of payoff functions which

a result which characterizes a mathematical equivalent to the relationship determined by

is

dominance theorem. Section 3.3 extends the

result to the case

of conditional stochastic

dominance.

3.1

A

Unified

In this section,

Framework for

we

Stochastic

Dominance

introduce the framework which

we

will use to discuss stochastic

dominance

theorems as an abstract class of theorems, and to draw precise parallels between stochastic dominance theorems and other types of theorems.

Let us Stochastic

first

consider another well-known example of a stochastic dominance theorem, First Order

Dominance (FOSD). This theorem can be

(where IA (s)

stated as follows

is

the indicator

function for the set A):

Proposition 3.1 (i)

(ii)

The following two conditions are equivalent for

For all n e

n

For all y e

TO

s {k\k

:

9i



% nondecreasing},

M

T FO m {y\y(s) = I

(s),

This theorem has the same structure as the functions are illustrated in Figure are nondecreasing in

8

1.

ae

Sfi},

J

all

F(;0)e A

1

K(s)dF(s;6)

jy(s)dF(s;6)

is

is

:

nondecreasing

nondecreasing

SOMSD theorem, Proposition 2. 1

'.

The

in ft

in ft

sets

of payoff

This theorem says that instead of checking that expected payoffs

for all nondecreasing payoff functions,

expected payoffs are nondecreasing in 6 for

all

10

IF

,

it is

payoff functions in the set

equivalent to check that

T FO

,

the set of indicator

The

functions of upper intervals.

easier to check that condition 1

- F(a;6),

The

of payoff functions

condition

is

is

much

smaller, and so condition

(ii) is

can be reduced to a restriction which requires that

(ii)

complement of the cumulative

the

requirement

latter

latter set

(i);

distribution function,

nondecreasing in 8 for a e

is

9?.

more standard way of stating FOSD.

the

There are many other examples of stochastic dominance theorems, some with multiple random

we

variables;

theorems

all

will discuss other

examples below

stochastic dominance theorems are characterized that the pair

(IT™,

r

F0

(U SOM T SOM )

satisfies the

)

same

theorem." If that statement

is true,

will use the abstract definition to

and how

that class of

then

make

and

different (11,0 pairs.

To make

relationship.

"A pair of sets

definition of the statement

by

satisfies a particular relationship; the

,

In general, stochastic dominance

in Section 4.5.

illustrated in Propositions 2.1'

have a parallel structure, as

FOSD

3.1.

The

However,

different

SOMSD theorem states

theorem

states that the pair

we

introduce a formal

this relationship precise,

of payoff functions, (n,D, satisfies a stochastic dominance

we

dominance

will say that (11,0 is a stochastic

pair.

We

statements about the class of stochastic dominance theorems,

We allow for multidimensional

theorems relates to other classes of theorems.

payoff functions and probability distributions, using the following notation: the set of probability distributions

on

SR" is

we

parameter space 0, distributions

F

:

x

9?"

denoted A", with typical element F:SR n

—»[0,1].

will use the notation A"

e to represent the set



such that such that F(;0) e A" for

[0,1]

all

Further, for a given

of parameterized probability

ds 0.

Definition 3.1 Consider a pair of sets of payoff functions (TI,r), with typical elements

K 9T —> SR and y :

and

:

9?"

—> SR.

The pair

(II, T) is

are equivalent for all parameter spaces

(ii)

(i)

For all ttgU,

(ii)

For all y eT,

Further,

we define the

j

n(s)dF(s;6) y(s)dF(s;6)

is

is

J

set I. SDT to

be the

set

a stochastic dominance pair with a partial order

nondecreasing nondecreasing

and all

conditions

if

(i)

n

F € Ae

:

in 6.

in 6.

of all (11,0 pairs which are stochastic dominance

pairs, as

follows:

2 5Dr = {(II,r)|(n,r) Thus,

when

a given (11,0 pair

is

is

a stochastic dominance pair}

a stochastic dominance

pair,

we write

(II, T)

Definition 3.1 clarifies the structure of stochastic dominance theorems.

e Z SDr

.

Stochastic dominance

theorems identify pairs of sets of payoff functions which have the following property: given a

parameterized

probability

lAn(s)dF(s\6)\iz

e

II

>

distribution

F, checking that

all

of the functions in the set

are nondecreasing is equivalent to checking that all of the functions in the set

11

(fy(s)dF(.s;0)|y

er|

T is

general, the set

Stochastic dominance theorems are useful because, in

are nondecreasing.

smaller than the set

II.

We can think of this definition as a statement about the equality of two sets. set

First, let

us define the

of admissible parameter spaces for the property "nondecreasing" together with probability

distributions parameterized

VND = {(F,0)|© has a Now, we can

on those spaces

partial order

and

as follows:

F e Ane j

rephrase the definition as follows: (11,0

j(F,0) €

VN M 7r(s)dF(s;d) is nondecreasing on

|(F,0) e

VND \JY(s)dF(s;0) is nondecreasing on

V/r e Ili

n

Vy e Ij

existing literature generally

J

7t(s)dF(s) and

Si. In contrast,

functional

a stochastic dominance pair if

n

Definition 3.1 differs from the existing literature

viewing

is

J

(i.e.,

=

Brumelle and Vickson, 1975),

compares the expected value of two 7t(s)dG(s) as

two

different linear functionals

by parameterizing the probability

distribution

J

when we

distributions to the reals,

become more

and stochastic

P theorems, for other properties P (such as supermodularity). specific

set of

many

are

The

utility

of this

formalize the relationship between stochastic dominance

examples of pairs of

sets

of payoff functions which satisfy stochastic

dominance theorems, we summarize three univariate stochastic dominance theorems are potentially

we

dominance theorems and stochastic supermodularity

definition will

To provide

to

n(s)dF{s\6) as a bilinear

theorems, an analogy which would not be obvious using the standard constructions. clear

F and G,

mapping payoff functions

and viewing

mapping payoff functions and (parameterized) probability

able to create an analogy between stochastic

in that the

probability distributions, say

in

Table

It.

There

other univariate stochastic dominance theorems (for example, theorems where the

payoff functions imposes restrictions on the third derivative of the payoff function); however,

we will

simply report the three most familiar univariate stochastic dominance theorems here.

12

TABLED COMPONENTS OF UNIVARIATE STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE THEOREMS"

Sets of Payoff Functions, II

U F0 = {n\n

(i)

n 5° s {n\n

(ii)

:

:

SR

SR

% nondecreasing} -> % concave}

r F°={ r \y(s) = I

->

[a

Yl

SOM

= \n

k

SR

:

—»

SR,

nondecreasing,



(s),aeX} )

r S0 ={Y\Hs) = -s} u{y|y(.y)

(iii)

T

Sets of Payoff Functions,

i

= min(a,s), aeSRJ

r «w _ |y| y (j) _ min(fl,s),

1

a e 9?}

concave

Each

(II,r) pair in

Table

II (iii)

corresponds to a 3.1

and Table It is

(ii).

Table

II is

a (univariate) stochastic dominance pair.

corresponds to a

SOMSD theorem,

FOSD theorem, Proposition 3.1.

and only

K{s)dF{s;8)

that

depend on

\min(a,s)dF(s;d)

if

6.

shown

now

Let us

1

in Proposition 2.

',

while Table

illustrate the interpretation

II (i)

of Definition

with a third example: Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD), shown in Table

II

known

is

J

if

as

Observe

is

nondecreasing in 6 for

all

nondecreasing in 8 for

that both y(s)

= s and

the distribution to be both nonincreasing

y(s)

= -s

univariate,

all

II

concave payoff functions

aeSi, and \sdF(s;6) does not

are included in

Tso

this forces the

;

and nondecreasing, and hence constant

mean of

in 6.

There are many other stochastic dominance theorems in addition to the univariate examples given above. Levy and Paroush (1974) derive results for bivariate functions, while these results and examines

some of these

some

multivariate stochastic

results in Section 4.5,

Meyer (1990) extends

dominance theorems as

where the main objective

is to

well.

We will report

apply these results to problems of

stochastic supermodularity.

Exact Conditions for a Stochastic Dominance Theorem

3.2

In this section,

dominance

statement that 3.2.1

and

we

study necessary and sufficient conditions for the pair

(11,1") to

be a stochastic

We want to specify the exact mathematical relationship which is equivalent to the (II, T) e Z sor We will first discuss our result and its implications; then, in Sections

pair.

.

3.2.2,

The main

we will provide the mathematical

result

of this section

is that (II,

arguments underlying the

T) e

the closure (under an appropriate topology) of the

13

I, SDT if

and only

if

result.

the following statement

convex cone of II u {1,-1}

is

is true:

equal to the closure

(under that topology) of the convex cone of

two constant

functions,

{n{s)

=

1}

Tu {1,-1},

where {1,-1} denotes the

set containing the

u {it{s) = -1}. We formalize this using the following notation:

cc(nu {1,-1}) = cc(ru {1,-1})

(3.1)

In the context of specific sets of payoff functions

n, the existing

literature identifies similar, but

stronger sufficient conditions for the corresponding stochastic dominance theorems, using a restrictive notion

of closure

(i.e.,

a topology with

more open

sets)

than the one which

below. For example, Brumelle and Vickson (1975) argue that (3.1)

shown

Table

in

this paper,

II to

we

will identify

sufficient for the {Yl,T) pairs

be stochastic dominance pairs under the topology of monotone convergence. In

we have developed for a

using the abstract definition

able to formally prove that the sufficient conditions hypothesized in fact sufficient for

is

more

we

are

by Brumelle and Vickson (1975)

are

dominance

"stochastic

pair,"

any stochastic dominance theorem, not just particular examples. Further, the

result that (3.1) is also necessary for (Tl,T) to

be a stochastic dominance pair

is

a

new

contribution of

this paper.

We now method.

argue that this result

First,

observe that unless

tells

T is

us

when we cannot do

a subset of n, there

is

theorems provide conditions which are easier to check than jrell. For example,

n

might be much

and

which

is

larger,

might be a it

set

which

is

J

better than the closed

no guarantee

to find a subset, T,

dominance theorems, as defined

in Definition 3.1, are

closed convex cone. For example, in the case of FOSD,

6

most

Its

for all

closed convex cone

of that closed convex cone for

easier to check that expected payoffs are nondecreasing in 6.

stochastic

dominance

7C(s)dF(s;0) nondecreasing in

not a closed convex cone.

might not be possible

convex cone

that stochastic

Thus, (3.1) indicates that

likely to

we consider the

be useful when

of payoff functions

set

II is a II

F0 .

easy to verify that positive scalar multiples and convex combinations of nondecreasing functions

It is

are nondecreasing functions, as are limits of sequences or nets of nondecreasing functions. Finally,

constant functions are also in IT

When

F0 .

IT contains the constant functions

and

is

a closed convex cone, (3.1) becomes:

n = cc(ru{l,-l}) In principle, the

most useful

general, there will not

r FO

(3.2)

T

is

the smallest set

be a unique smallest

set.

To

whose closed convex cone

contains indicator functions of upper intervals.

combinations of elements of

T

FO

Q

However,

in

By

taking limits of sequences of convex

u {1,-1}, and appropriately scaling these functions, we can generate

any nondecreasing function. However,

where

is II.

see this, consider the case of FOSD, where the set

we can

represents the rationals, and note that

also define the set

14

n

F0

t FO = {y\y(s) = I[a „,($),

= cc(f F0 u {1,-1})

.

While f F0

a e q\,

c T FO

,

in

f F0 is not any easier to check. Thus, stochastic dominance theorems are that T is the smallest closed set whose closed convex cone is II; we will call such a

practice the smaller set

generally stated so set the

"extreme points" of II.

Finally, because (3.2) is necessary

n=cc(IIu{l,-l}), we know of II: there stochastic

is

no

we

that

and sufficient for (H,T)

smaller or easier-to-check closed set

dominance

convex cone method

pair.

is

This

is

F

1

higher Gower) than

n in

neither inequality holds for all

we

first

We

cc(IIu{l,-l}).

distributions in the

the set of extreme points

that

we have proved

(II,

f)

is

a

that the closed

show

then

we

that II

show

same way

same. In Section 3.2.2,

II,

if

that

dominance

that (3.1) characterizes stochastic

Consider the problem of ordering two probability distributions,

Section 3.1.1,

T be

of payoff functions, f, such that

the "right" approach.

payoff functions II orders if

be a stochastic dominance pair when

what we mean when we say

two subsections, we prove

In the next

to

cannot do any better than letting

then

F2

we

if

F

1

and

\7r(s)dF\s)

F

2 ,

where we say

> (

< £ k where there

We

0.

is

a neighborhood corresponding to each

will return to clarify the relationship

between

this

topology and other topologies in the discussion following Theorem 3.4, below.

Let cc(A) denote the convex cone of a set A, and topology

is

=

\ndii

The proof of

is

linear

and continuous in

lemma

is

mathematical results in this paper build upon

it.

simple lemma.

3.2

A

denote the closure of

understood to be a^P*,?^) in the discussion below, unless noted).

that the functional P(7t,^i)

Lemma

let

this

its first

elementary, but

Consider a set of payofffunctions jl &g>:

II

we

A

(where the

We now use the fact

argument to prove the following state

it

here because

all

of the

cP». Then the following two conditions are

equivalent for all (i)

For all n e

II,

\nd\i> 0.

7 The boundedness assumption guarantees that the integral of the payoff function exists. It is possible to place other restrictions on the payoff functions and the space of finite signed measures so that the pair is a separated duality, in which case the arguments below would be unchanged; for example, it is possible to restrict the payoff functions and the signed measures using a "bounding function." For more discussions of separated dualities, see Bourbaki (1987, p. n.41).

16

(ii)

For all 7tecc(Uu

Proof:

First,

we show

{1,-1}),

(i)

jnd/i>0.

implies

Fix a measure fieg'. Then the following implications

(ii).

hold:

For all K ell,

=>

(Since

J

d[i

Forall ;rellu

= -j

dji

Forall

[tt, rf/z

>

{1,-1},

J;rd/i>0

= 0).

=>

(Since

jndn>0

and J

ff€cc(nu {l.-l}), J^d//>0

n2 dfi>0

implies

[a,^, J

+ a2 7T2 ]

d/i

= a^TTi

d\i

+ a 2 \n 2 dfi>0

when a,,a 2 >0). =>

For a// K ecc(IIu{l,-l}), J7rd// >

(Recall that for a continuous function/, the half-space [x

That

(ii)

implies

e

(i)

9^|jc

> 0}

is

follows because IT

Lemma 3.2 can be restated another way: is

exactly the

same

/(A)

c /(A).

The implication then follows because

closed, and the linear functional P(;/l) is continuous for all

c cc(II u {1,-1}).

the set of measures

as the set of measures

[i

e£*

for

//

which

/*.)

£?.£.£>.

e^» for which jndfi >

Jtt^ >

for all

it

e

for all

cc(Il

7T

e

II

u {1,-1}).

Formally,

{/i€^-|J^d/x>0 V;renj = {//Gf* IJ^rd/t

As

V;recc(IIu{l,-l})}

discussed above, because positive scalar multiples do not reverse the inequalities and because

the functional

fi is

linear in its second argument, the latter equality is equivalent to the following:

FKF^A^JTrdF^JKdF2 Vn e III That

>0

is,

for any

two probability

= If^F2 eA^TtdF

distributions, II orders the

cc(IIu{l,-l}).

17

1

two

ZJndF

2

V/r e cc(II

u {!,- 1})

distributions exactly the

same

as

we

Building from this lemma, characterization of stochastic in Section 4. (ii)

implies

turn to prove the

dominance theorems,

main mathematical theorem underlying

This theorem makes use of the linearity of the functional

(i)

relies

on

Lemma

3.2,

the

as well as the characterizations of other properties

while the proof that

(i)

implies

/J(tt,jU) in n. (ii)

The proof

that

makes use of a standard

which determines the meaning of

separating hyperplane argument. Note that the choice of topology,

closure, is critical for the application of the separating hyperplane theorem.

Theorem

P

t .

Consider a pair of sets of payofffunctions Then the following two conditions are equivalent: 3.3

(II, I*),

where

(i)

lii€$'\J7tdn>0 V;rell} = j/ie£-|Jy^>0 Vyerj.

(ii)

cc(U u {1,-1}) = cc(r u {1,-1}).

Proof: First consider

we

(ii)

implies

(i).

Suppose

that

II

and T are

subsets of

cc(IIu {1,-1}) = cc(Tkj {1,-1}). Then

have:

j//

e

2'|Jffd!/i

VTrellj

£

= |/X6f*|J^d//>0 V;recc(IIu{l,-l})j (By

Lemma 3.2.) = In e -f ^jydfi >

V76cc(ru{l,-1})}

(By assumption.)

= {nep\jydfi>0 (By

Vyer}

Lemma 3.2.)

Now we prove that (i) implies (ii).

Define II

Suppose (without loss of generality) the

(XP'&P) topology

from above {p(-,H)\fi

that the set

is

= cc(U u {1,-1}) and F = cc(T u {1,-1}).

that there exists a

y e f such that y e

fl

.

We know that

generated from a family of open, convex neighborhoods. Recall

of continuous linear functionals on P»

sTX'}. Using these

facts,

is

exactly the set

a corollary to the Hahn-Banach theorem8 implies that

8 See Dunford and Schwartz (1957, p. 421), Kothe (1969, p. 244) for discussions of the relevant theorems about the separation of convex sets. See also McAfee and Reny (1992) for a related application of the Hahn-Banach theorem, where the separating hyperplane also takes the form of an element of J*.

18

since fl

is

closed and convex, there exists a constant c and a

hyperplane)so that P(x,n.) > c for Since {1,-1} € fl and

argue

we can

take c

hypothesis that

/J(7T,/i.)

Because {1,-1} e and thus j J^,


c

ft,

and

Thus,

for

Ke

all

ft.



So,

e 7JF (a separating

c.

> c. Now we

=

/?(0, /x.)

But, f}(pk,iL.)

ft.

we

let

c

=

will

= pc

).

T2 but since x2 ,

T,

cT

2 ),

first

is

the closure of a set

A

ff .

under %2

(

.

Thus,

if

This implies Q.E.D.

3.4.

note that, given two topologies

true because the finer topology has

we know

A = AT

that

-A*

2

) is

more closed

T,

and r2 where ,

z, is

contained in the closure of A

A T is finer, there might be a closed set which is a strict subset of A This

"P*,

c

cc(nu{l,-l}) r =cc(ru{l,-l}) T ,then cc(nu{l,-l}) a =cc(ru{l,-l})

To

«

then (11,0

pair.

Tl

sets;

is

a closed set under

but that

still

contains

the linear functionals

/?(7T,/x)


SR and y

:

9?"



SR.

Let

K be a collection of subsets of

conditional stochastic dominance pair

a partial order and all

F 9T x :

->

[0, 1]

if

conditions

k{G\K)

yeT and all KeK,

y(6\K)

For all neU. and all

(ii)

For all

(i)

and

with typical elements

9?".

(ii)

Then the pair (TIX)

are equivalent for all

such that such that F{;6) e A" :

KeK,

(i)

(II, T),

We now extend Theorem 3.4.

23

is

is

nondecr easing

in 6.

nondecreasing

in 6.

is

a

K-

with

Theorem 3.5 Consider a pair of sets of payofffunctions

P

1 .

Let

K

he a collection of subsets of 9t\ where

(Yl,T),

where

II

and T are

subsets of

€ K. Then the following two conditions

9?"

are equivalent:

The pair (TIT)

(i)

cc(II

(ii)

Proof:

is

a ^-conditional stochastic dominance pair.

u {1,-1}) = ccOTu {1,-1}).

We can apply the proof of Theorem 3.4 almost exactly.

likewise for Tk.

Then note

that

cc(U K u{IK ,-IK }) = cc(TK implies

(ii)

show

(i).

that if

One example of a

To show

(ii) fails,

u {IK ,-IK })

that

then

cc(Ilu{l,-l})

(i)

(i)

implies

must

conditional stochastic

= cc(T u {1,-1})

for all K. Then, for every

IK \n

e

II},

and

K we apply Theorem 3.4,

the arguments of Theorem 3.4 can be used to

(ii),

for the case

fail

n^ = {n

Let

implies that

where

K=

9?".

Q.E.D.

dominance theorem which has appeared

in various

forms in

the literature (see Whitt (1982)) involves the set of nondecreasing payoff functions, as follows:

Theorem 3.6 The following conditions are For all

(i)

it

:

9?"

—» 9?

equivalent:

nondecreasing and

all sublattices

#c 91",

k(6\K)

is

nondecreasing

in 6. (ii)

For

all increasing sets

nondecreasing

Ac 9?"

and all

sublattices isfc 9?",

f JAnK

dG(s;6,K)

is

in 6.

Proof: Apply Theorem 3.5 together with the fact that cc({k\k nondecreasing}

This theorem that

condition (for

(ii) is

A (s)

\I

nondecreasing}

u {1,-1}).

Q.E.D.

usually proved using algebraic arguments; but using the results of this paper,

follows as an immediate corollary of

it

Order

is

u {1,-1}) = cc({IA

Theorem

3.5.

First, take the

equivalent to requiring that F(s;6) satisfies the

case where

we

see

n-1. Then

Monotone Likelihood Ratio (MLR)

a proof, see Whitt (1980)), defined as follows:

The parameter 6 indexes the probability distribution F(;6) e A according the Monotone Likelihood Ratio Order (MLR) if, for all 6 > H L there exist numbers

Definition 3.2

1

to

,

-oo 9? and y

conditions (i)

(i)

and

:

—» 91.

9?"

The pair

(II, T) is

For all n sU,

Jt(s)dF(s;6)

f

is

with typical elements

a stochastic supermodularity pair

are equivalent for all lattices

(ii)

(II, F),

© and all F e A"e

supermodular

if

:

in 6.

Js (ii)

Further, pairs,

For all yeT,

we

define the set

analogous to

"L

sm

(U SOM ,r SOM )ismI. !lsr

When comparing

.

[

y(s)dF(s;6)

Z J5r To

to

is

be the

supermodular

set

of

all (II,r)

in 6.

pairs

which

are stochastic supermodularity

place our example from Proposition 3.3 in this framework, the pair

.

Definition 3.1 (stochastic dominance theorem) and Definition 4.1 (stochastic

supermodularity theorem),

it is

helpful to recall that stochastic

dominance theorems and

stochastic

supermodularity theorems are both characterized by (11,0 pairs corresponding to sets of linear functionals of the

Thus,

it is

form

f5(K,-),

which are then composed with parameterized probability

distributions.

possible to compare the two types of theorems directly, even though in a stochastic

dominance theorem, the parameter space theorem, the parameter space

is

any

is

any

lattice.

26

set

with a partial order, while in a stochastic dominance

.

More

we

generally,

can define a class of theorems called Stochastic

defined for an arbitrary property P.

Qp

which are defined so

on 0/' is all

that,

P

Theorems, which are

We are interested in properties P together with parameter spaces

given a function h

:

P

—> 9t,

the statement "h(6) satisfies property

Qp

well-defined and takes on the following values: "true" or "false." Let

such parameter spaces 0,,

Further, for a given property P,

.

we

P

denote the set of

will define the set of admissible

parameter spaces together with probability distributions parameterized on those spaces: n

VP = {(F,e p )\e p

e

e p and F e A%

p

}

Definition 4.2 Consider a pair of sets of payoff functions (IT,r), with typical elements

K

:

SK"

—> 9? and

7:9?"

—> 9?.

(F,Q P ) e

equivalent for all (i)

For all 7teTl,

(ii)

For

j

yeT,

all

f Js

The pair

Vp

(II,

O w a stochastic P pair

is

y(s)dF(s;6) satisfies property

we

let I. SPT

be the

analogous to stochastic dominance,

l(F,e) e

Vp \J7t(s)dF(s;6)

satisfies

= |(F,0) e v;\jy(s)dF(s;G)

In the next section,

e n,

of

set

P on

satisfies

all

(i)

and

(ii)

are

on

P

on 0„.

can be any convex

n(s)dF{s;6)

all

.

stochastic

is

set,

and condition

concave in 6."

P pairs

As

(i)

of

in the case of

for a given property P.

Also

we can rewrite the requirement of Defintion 4.2 as follows: Vtt e

nj

V/ € rl

P on

stochastic

cone method of proving stochastic dominance

P theorems, if P is a closed convex cone property.

The Closed Convex Cone Approach

we

J

we show that the closed convex

theorems can be extended to

4.2

tt

0,,

©p

P

7t(s)dF(s;6) satisfies property

interpreted, "For all

stochastic dominance,

conditions

:

For example, for a stochastic concavity theorem, Definition 4.2

if

is

Valid for all

CCC Properties

which we

call

"Closed Convex Cone" (CCC)

properties, such that the following statement is true: for all properties

P which are CCC, if a pair (IIJ)

In this section,

is

identify a class of properties,

a stochastic dominance pair, then (tl.D

is

a stochastic

closed convex cone method of proving stochastic

P

pair; thus, for all

P theorems is valid.

CCC

This result

is

properties, the

useful because

allows us to use the existing theorems from the stochastic dominance literature to generate classes of theorems.

CCC properties are properties are defined as follows:

27

it

many new

A property P is a CCC property (written P eCCC) if the set offunctions —> SR which satisfy P forms a closed convex cone, where closure is taken with respect to the topology of pointwise convergence, and if constant functions satisfy P.

Definition 4.3

g

Qp

Note while

we

functions,

The

we

that

are using closure under the topology of pointwise convergence for properties P,

weak topology

are using closure under the

(as defined in Section 3.1.1) for sets of payoff

n and T.

properties nondecreasing, concave, and supermodular are all

CCC

properties, as is the

property "constant." Further, any property which places a sign restriction on a mixed partial derivative is

CCC.

Finally, since the intersection of

two closed convex cones

of these properties can be combined to yield another

"nondecreasing

and

convex"

CCC

CCC

a

is

is itself

For example, the property

property.

This

property.

useful in the context of comparative statics for the following reason.

/i:SR—»SR andg:9?"

—>SR.

If h(x) is

n in II,

and 6

nondecreasing and convex in 6 for

all

supermodular and monotone), then

7t(s)dF(s;g(y))

is

is

is

property

is

Consider two functions,

convex and nondecreasing, and g(y)

monotone (nondecreasing or nonincreasing), then h(g(y))

J

a closed convex cone, any

is

supermodular. Thus,

supermodular and if f K(s)dF{s\6) is

by 6 - g(y) (where g

is

dominance pair, then (H,T)

is

in fact determined

supermodular in

y.

Now we prove a result which builds from Theorem 3.4: Theorem

Suppose property

4.1

a stochastic

P pair.

PeCCC.

If (11,0 is a stochastic

u {1,-1}) = cc{T u {1,-1}),

Equivalently, if cc(Jl

then (FIX)

is

a stochastic

pair.

Proof:

For all

=» (Since

J

dF(s;6)

=>

\[ajz

x

(s)

ell, ^K{s)dF(s;0) satisfies P.

For all n e

II

u {1,-1},

= 1, and constant functions For all n e

jn^s) dF(s;6)

(Since

it

satisfies

cc(Jl

x

=>

{1,

satisfies P.

satisfy P, for all

P eCCC).

-1} ),

J

x(s)dF(s;6) satisfies P.

P and jn2 (s) dF(s;6)

+ a2 K2 {s)] dF(s;6) = a \n

a,,a2 > 0, since

u

f K{s)dF(s;0) Js

{s) x

satisfies

P implies

dF(s;6) + a2 JK2 (s) dF(s;6) satisfies

P is a CCC property). For all K e cc(IIu {1,-1}),

28

J

n(s)dF(s;0) satisfies P.

P for

P

.

(Recall that a subset of a topological space

convergent nets of elements in that all 11,

for

JKa (s) [

dF(s;6

7t(s)dF(s;6)

satisfies

Ka

any net

P

)

is

in cc(Il

u {1,-1})

-» $7i(s) dF(s;6

)

is

closed

if

and only

if

it

contains the limits of all the

Since the linear functional fi(;fi)

na —> n

such that

(Kothe, 1969, p.l

,

6

then given

Since

1).

the pointwise limit of a net of functions

which

P

a

is

is

continuous for

,

CCC property,

For all yecc(ru{l,-l}),

(By Theorem

3.6, since

=>

K(s)dF(s;0)

satisfy P, then j

(n.O

is

J

y(s)dF(s;6) satisfies P.

a stochastic dominance

For all y e T, j y(s)dF(s;6)

pair.)

satisfies P.

T Q cc(T u {1,-1}))

Precisely analogous arguments establish the symmetric implication.

This theorem generates

many new

been identified in the large case, this

and

as well.)

=>

(Since

set. 10

literature

theorem generalizes a

to nondecreasing functions

classes of stochastic

Q.E.D.

P theorems, where the

(11,0 pairs which have

on stochastic dominance are also stochastic

result

by Topkis (1968), who proves

and indicator functions of nondecreasing

P pairs. As a special

that the (11,0 pair corresponding sets, respectively, is

a stochastic

P pair for P in CCC. What we have shown stochastic

P pairs,

Y SDT = E J/T

.

In

then

in this section is that if

£ JDr c Z Jpr However,

Remark 2

.

at

Z JDr c ^ SFr

-

property, the property "constant in 6."

nondecreasing payoff functions, and the set constant theorem," since j 7t(s)dF(s;d)

However, (I1 F0 T) ,

properties

which

note that not

then end of Section 4.4,

"nondecreasing and convex," then

CCC

P is a CCC property,

is

For now,

T = -IT

properties

.

dominance

10 See Kothe (1969, pp. 10-11) for a proof of this statement.

spT

P

denotes the set of in

CCC

all

are such that

P

argue that

let

us consider a simpler example of a

The

pair.

IT

F0

pair (IT

6 if and only

will satisfy equivalence relationships.

29

ro

l,

we

Take the case of

constant in

clearly is not a stochastic

all

and

if

when

the property

the set of

,

FO ,

T)

univariate,

satisfies a "stochastic

-\n(s)dF(s;d)

The next

all

is

is

constant in

6.

section identifies a class of

Linear Difference Properties

4.3

This section characterizes a subset of

CCC properties, which we call Linear Difference Properties we

(LDPs). These properties are interesting because, as

will

show

in Section 4.4, for all

P in LDP,



T.

(4.1)

Combining the "closed

(4. 1)

with Theorem 3.4,

convex cone" method

P is an LDP.

That

is, if

Pe LDP, LDPs

Important examples of

Supermodularity predictions.

We

is

is

we can

then

(II,

OeZ „ s

are supermodular

important because of

also

conclude

that, just as in the

case of stochastic dominance,

P theorems when = cc(ru{l,-l}).

exactly the right one for the study of stochastic

emphasize the

if

and only

if

cc(IIu{l,-l})

and concave; others are summarized

role in the analysis of

its

in

Table

monotone comparative

I.

statics

about concavity, since concavity and convexity are also

result

frequently encountered in economic contexts; for example, if an objective function is concave, then the First

Order Conditions characterize the optimum. Further, concavity can be used to establish the

existence of supporting prices in a resource allocation problem.

The

result described in equation (4.1) is useful

(II, T) is

because

dominance; by

(4.1),

checking to see

if (II

,D

is

this set II

easier to verify whether or not

same

are determined by an economic problem, and

has been analyzed in the stochastic dominance literature, then the corresponding stochastic

supermodularity theorem

r have

may be

a stochastic dominance pair answers the

question. For example, if the characteristics of a set II

not

it

a stochastic supermodularity pair by drawing from the existing literature on stochastic

the

is

immediate. This allows us to bypass the step of checking whether II and

same closed convex cone direcdy

(further,

most of the stochastic dominance

literature

does

(LDPs). The

first

make such a statement explicitly).

We now begin to build our formal definition of Linear Difference Properties important feature of LDPs

is that

they can be represented in terms of sign restrictions on inequalities

involving linear combinations of the function evaluated at different parameter values. For example, H L L if and only if g(6 ) - g(d ) > for all 6" > 6 in 0. This statement g(0) is nondecreasing on specifies a set of inequalities,

where each inequality

high parameter value and a low parameter value. if

and only

x

if

g(6

a difference between the function evaluated another example, g(d)

v 6 2 )- g(6') + gtf a0 2 )- g(d 2 )>0 1

specifies a set of inequalities, this time involving the

In both cases,

is

To take

for all

sum of two

we can represent every inequality by

6\6

2

in

0.

is

at

a

supermodular on

Again,

this

statement

differences.

the parameter values

and the coefficients which

on the corresponding function values. For example, for the property nondecreasing, each inequality involves the coefficient vector (1,-1) and a parameter vector of the form (d H ,8 L ), where 1 is are placed

the coefficient

on g(d") and -1

is

the coefficient

30

on g(6

L ).

Thus, g(6)

is

nondecreasing on

if

and

only

for

if

^aig

{