On closed categories of functors - University of Rochester Mathematics

Report 0 Downloads 37 Views
ON CLOSED CATEGORIES

OF FUNCTORS

Brian Day Received November 7, 19~9 The purpose of the present paper is to develop in further detail the remarks, extensions

concerning

the relationship

to closed structures

"Enriched

functor categories"

on functor categories,

| 1] §9.

is familiar with the basic results including the representation

of Kan functor

It is assumed that the reader

of closed category theory,

theorem.

mentioned below, the terminology

made in

Apart from some minor changes

and notation employed are those of

|i], |3], and |5]. Terminology A closed category will be called a normalised normalisation. normalised

Throughout

V in the sense of Eilenberg and Kelly |B| closed category, V: V o ÷ En6 being the this paper V is taken to be a fixed

symmetric monoidal

closed category

(Vo, @, I, r, £, a, c,

V, |-,-|, p) with V ° admitting all small limits colimits

(direct limits).

V

closed category

(with possibly

choice has been made of it.

those hypotheses

large domain)

"natural"

In short, we place on

sets Ens as a ground category and are closed categories.

As in [i], an end in B of a V-functor T: A°P@A ÷ B is a

Y-natural

property

and

exists

which both allow it to replace the cartesian

of (small)

satisfied by most

limits)

It is further supposed that if the limit

or colimit in ~o of a functor then a definite

(inverse

family mA: K ÷ T(AA) of morphisms

that the family B(1,mA):

in B o with the

B(BK) ÷ B(B,T(AA))

in V o is

-2-

universally

V-natural in A for each B 6 B; then an end in V turns out

to be simply a family sA: K ~ T(AA) universally

V-natural in A.

of morphisms

in V o which is

The dual concept is called a coend.

From [i] we see that the choice of limits and collmlts made in V o determines

a definite

end and coend of each V-functor

T: A°P®A ÷ V for which such exist. SA: fAT(AA)

~ T(AA)

now construct,

These are denoted by

and sA: T(AA) ÷ fAT(AA)

respectively.

for each pair A, B of V-categories

definite

V-category

[A,B] having

objects,

and having [A,B](S,T)

V-functors

VSA: V;AB(SA,TA)

than the family

An element

under the projections

÷ Bo(SA,TA) , to a V-natural

mA: SA ÷ TA in the sense of [3].

family of morphlsms

It is convenient

{a A} of its components,

of V-functors

to call a, rather

a V-natural transformation

from S to T; for then the underlying ordinary the category

with A small, a

S, T, ...: A + B as its

= ~AB(SA,TA).

E V;AB(SA,TA ) clearly corresponds,

We can

category

[A,B] o i_~s

and V-natural transformations.

Limits and colimits

in the functor category

always be computed evaluationwlse,

[A,B] wlll

so that the choice of limits and

colimlts made in V fixes a choice in [A,V]

for each small

V-category

A.

of cotensoring

and

Included in this rule are the concepts

tensoring,which

were seen in |5] to behave

like limits and collmits

respectively. In order to replace the category normalised

closed category

terminology.

A V-monoidal

of sets by the given

V, we shall "lift" most of the usual category ~ is a V-category

A together with

a M-functor @: A@A + A, an object Y • A, and V-natural isomorphisms a: (A@B)@C a A@(B@C),

~: A @ I a A,snd r: Y@A a A, satisfying

usual coherence

for a monoidal

axioms

and MC3 of [3]. (chosen) right

If, furthermore, M-adJoints

the

category - namely axioms MC2

-@A and A@-: A ÷ A both have

for each A • A, then ~ is called a

M-biclosed category

(see Lambek |8]).

V-monoidal

(A, @, I~ r, A, a) is a V-natural isomorphism

category

c: A@B ~ B@A satisfying the coherence

A M-symmetry

for a

axioms MC6 and MC7 of [3].

Finally we come to the concept of a M-symmetric-monoidal-closed category which can be described

simply as a M-biclosed category

with a M-symmetry;

we do not insist on a "M-normalisation"

of this structure.

An obvious example of such a category

itself, where ~ is taken to be the M-functor Ten:

as part is M

M@M ÷ M defined in

[ 3] Theorem 111.6.9. We note here that, the symbol

S: A ÷ C and T: B ÷ P,

S@T may have two distinct meanings.

the canonical pair)

for M-functors

M-functor

A®B

~

C@D which sends the object

(A,B) • A@B to the object

Proposition

III.3.2.

In general

it is

(ordered

(SA,TB) • C@D, as defined in [3]

When C and P are both M, however,

we shall

also use S@T to denote the composite S@T A@B

Ten ~

V@M

~

The context always clearly indicates Henceforth we work enti~el~ unqualified words

"cate~ory"~

etc. mean "M-category",

V.

the meaning. over M and suppose that the

"functor"~

"M-functor",

"natural transformation"~

"V-natural

transformatlon"~

etc.

-4 -

i.

Introduction

Let A be a small category subcategory

of |A,V],

identifying

and regard

A 6 A °p with the left r e p r e s e n t e d

functor LA: A ÷ V in the usual way. canonical

expansion

(adequacy) biclosed

A °p as a full

For each S 6 |A,V]

we have the

(see |l]) S ~ ~AsA@LA w h i c h asserts

the density

of A °p in |A,V].

category V then,

S@T of @: [A,V]®|A,V]

If [A,V|

in view of this expansion,

÷ |A,V]

the values LA@T, b e c a u s e

has the structure

at (S,T) is e s s e n t i a l l y

-@T has a right adJoint.

of a

the value d e t e r m i n e d by

These in turn are

d e t e r m i n e d by the values LA@L B, b e c a u s e each L A @ - has a right adJoint.

Writing

is e s s e n t i a l l y

P(ABC)

for (LA@LB)(c),

d e t e r m i n e d by the functor P: A ° P @ A ° P @ A ~ V, in the

same way that the m u l t i p l i c a t i o n by structure

we see that the functor

in a linear algebra

is d e t e r m i n e d

constants.

These c o n s i d e r a t i o n s a premonoldal

structure

on A.

suggest what is called in section This

consists

of functors

P: A ° P @ A ° P @ A

÷ V and J: A ÷ V, t o g e t h e r with certain n a t u r a l

isomorphisms

corresponding

rlght-ldentlty structure

morphlsms,

is a special

down, we collect

to a s s o c l a t i v i t y , w h i c h satisfy

case.

Before

left-ldentity,

suitable

attempting

in section 2 the properties

3

axioms;

and

a monoldal

to write the axioms

of ends and coends

that

we shall need. The main aim of this paper is to show that, premonoidal

structure

canonical b i c l o s e d

on a small category

structure

from a

A, there results

on the functor category

tA,V];

a this is

-5-

done in section 3. [A,V]

As one would expect, biclosed structures on

correspond biJectlvely to premonoldal structures on A to

within "isomorphism".

However we do not formally prove this

assertion, which would require the somewhat lengthy introduction of premonoldal functors to make it clear what "isomorphism" was intended. The concluding sections contain descriptions of some commonly occurring types of premonoidal structure on a (possibly large) category A.

The case in which the premonoidal structure is

actually monoidal is discussed in section 4.

In section 5 we

provide the data for a premonoidal structure which arises when the hom-obJects of A are comonoids

(@-coalgebras)

in V in a natural way.

In both cases the tensor-product and internal-hom formulas given in section 3 for the biclosed structure on [A,V| may be simplified to allow comparison with the corresponding formulas for some well-known examples of closed functor categories.

2.

Induced Natural Transformations

Natural transformations,

in both the ordinary and

extraordinary senses, are treated in [2]

and [3].

Our applications

of the rules governing their composition with each other

(and with

functors) are quite straightforward and will not be analysed in detail. The following dualisable lemmas on induced naturality are expressed in terms of coends. Lemma 2.1.

Let T: A°P~A@B + C be a functor and let

aAB: T(AAB) ÷ SB be a coend over A for each B E B.

Then there

-6-

exists a unique functor S: B ~ C makin~ the family ~AB natural in B. Proof.

For each pair B, B' E B consider the diagram SBB,

B(BB')

T(AA-)BB'

>

I

C(SB SB')

C(~,I)

C(T(AAB),T(AAB'))

~

C(T(AAB),SB')

,

C(l,~) Because C(s,l) is an end and C(I,a).T(AA-)BB , is natural in A we can define SBB , to be the unique morphism making this diagram commute.

The functor axioms VFI' and VF2' of [ 3| are easily

verified for this definition of S using the fact that C(~,I) is an end.

S is then the unique functor making ~AB natural in B. Lemma 2.2.

Let T: A°P@A@B * C and S,R: B ÷ C be functors,

let aAB: T(AAB) + SB be a coend over A, natural in B, and let

8AB:

T(AAB) + RB be natural in A and B.

Then the induced family

YB: SB ÷ RB is natural in B. Proof.

For each pair B, B' E B consider the

diagram

-7-

C(l,~) C(T(AAB),T(AAB'))

~

C(T(AAB),SB')

1

T(

~,i)

"~

C(l,y) \

/ B(BB')

\

,.

SBB, -.

~,

.~- C(SB,SB')

2

C(RB,RB')

~

C(T(AAB),RB')

C(SB,RB')

c(y,x) The commutatlvity the naturallty commutes

i and that of the exterior

in B of ~ and 8 respectively.

hence,

each pair B,B'

of region

because

C(e,1)

Region

is an end, region

express

2 clearly

3 commutes

for

6 B, as required.

By similar arguments Lemma 2.3.

we obtain

Let T: A°P@A@B°P@B

÷ C and S: B°P®B ÷ C ,,=

be functors t let eABB':

T(AABB')

÷ S(BB')

be a coend over A,

natural

in B and B', and let 8AB: T(AABB)

÷ C be natural

in A

and B.

T_hen the induced

÷ C is natural

in B.

Lemma 2.4, functors~ 8AB: T(AA)

YB: C ~ R(BB)

YB: S(BB)

Let T: A°P@A ÷ C and R: B°P@B ÷ C be

let CA: T(AA) * R(BB)

family

÷ C be a coend over A, and let

be natural

is natural

in B,

in A and B.

Then the induced

family

-8-

Let A b e whose

a category

coend sA: T(AA-)

and let T(AA-) be a functor into

÷ fAT(AA-)

over A E A exists

of the e x t r a variables

"-".

canonically

in these e x t r a variables.

functorlal

case where T(AA-) (with different this n o t a t i o n

Then, by Lemma 2.1,

~ S(A-)@T(A-)

variances

in A) we will

to sA: S(A-)@R(A-)

repeated

dummy variable

indicate

the domain of ~'. expressions

the dummy variables example,

V

abbreviate

S(A-)2R(A-)

to

formed entirely by the

to introduce

which we do not formalise

an e x p r e s s i o n

In the special

S and R into

the following

completely.

e x p r e s s i o n N w h i c h is formed by one or more uses corresponds

is

÷ S(A-)2R(A-) , leaving the

use of 2, it is convenient

considerations

for all values

fAT(AA-)

frequently

A in the e x p r e s s i o n

In order to handle repeated

for functors

V

To each

of 2, there

N in which each 2 is replaced by @,

in N b e c o m i n g r e p e a t e d

if N is (RA2S(AB))2T(BC)

variables

for functors

in N; for

R: A ÷ V,

S: A°P@B ~ V, and T: B°P@c ÷ V, then N is (RA@S(AB))@T(BC). Moreover,

there

is a canonical

q = qN: N ÷ N defined, occurrences

as follows,

of @ in N. - -

natural t r a n s f o r m a t i o n by i n d u c t i o n

If N contains

- -

on the n u m b e r of

no occurrence

of @ then

m

N ~ N and qN = i; otherwise N = N'@N" and qN is the composite N'@N"

~ N'@N" q'@q"

In the above example, (RA@S(AB))@T(BC)

~ N'@N". s

q is the composite ~ (RA2S(AB))@T(BC)

s@l and this is n a t u r a l

~ (RA2S(AB))@T(BC) s

in A, B,snd C; we say that the variables

and B are "summed out" by q.

A

The path qN: N ÷ N is in fact all those

variables

in N w h i c h

Le_~..

are

summed

~

qN:

in all the r e p e a t e d N ÷ N.

transformation

Then

result three

This

of @ in N.

is trivial;

V and let

is~

in p a r t i c u l a r ,

in N which

are

for a unique

is by i n d u c t i o n If N contains

othe~ise

summed

out

natural

N = N'@N"

on the n ~ b e r

no o c c u r r e n c e

of of @ the

and we can factor

f in

steps: q'@l

N

as g ' q N

over

g: N ÷ M.

Proo=~f. occurrences

f factors

into

which

variables

coend

out by qN:

Let M be a functor

f: N ÷ M be a n a t u r a l _ t r a n s f o r m a t i o n natural

a multiple

= N'@N"

l@q" )

N'@N"

s >

N'@N"

~ N'@N"

= N

M

First

consider

the t r a n s f o ~

tensor-hom

adJunction

hypothesis

and routine

w(f):

isomorphism naturality

N' ÷ [N",M] ~ = Vp of

of f under

V.

considerations,

By the i n d u c t i o n the d i a g r ~

q' N'

~ N'

[ N",M]

commutes

for a unique

morphlsm

~(f'): N' ÷ |N",M]

the

where

-10-

f': N'®N" by q'.

÷ M is n a t u r a l

Similarly

f' factors

f": N'@N"

~ M which

by e i t h e r

of q' or q".

as g.s

for a unique

remaining

in all the v a r i a b l e s

variables

as f".(l@q")

is n a t u r a l

not

summed

for a unique

in all the variables

Finally,

because

g: N ÷ M w h i c h

in N and M by Lemmas

morphism

not

s is a coend,

is n a t u r a l

out

summed

out

f" factors

in all the

2.2,

2.3,

and 2.4.

m

Combining

these

steps•

in the r e q u i r e d

we have

that

for a path q': N' ~ N'

is d e n o t e d part

by n.

of the

three

the

induced

f in Lemma induced

qN = s(q'@q")

cases

transformation

n: N ÷ N' is a n a t u r a l

form

g: N ÷ N'

are a n e c e s s a r y

category

and we c o n s i d e r

below.

if n: N ÷ N' is a n a t u r a l

from the coherent

2.5 is of the

transformations

of a p r e m o n o i d a l

special

First, entirely

Such

concept

relevant

through

manner.

W h e n the t r a n s f o r m a t i o n q'.n

f factors

isomorphism

data isomorphisms

isomorphism

a, r,

and is called

constructed

£, c of V then

an induced

m

coherence Lemma that the

isomorphism.

2.5,

and the o r i g i n a l

induced induced

determined shall

not

coherence coherence

coherence

isomorphisms isomorphism

by the a r r a n g e m e n t label

such

Secondly, natural

In view of the u n i q u e n e s s of a, r,

assertion

of

£, c, it is clear

are coherent.

In other words,

n: N + N' is completely

of @ in N and N';

consequently

we

isomorphisms. w h e n n z h@k:

transformations

S(A-)@R(A-)

÷ S'(A-)@R'(A-)

h: S ~ S' and k: R ÷ R',

let us w r i t e

for

-11

h@._k for h@k.

-

This not only makes the symbol @ En~-functorial

whenever it is defined on objects, but also makes the coend sA: S(A-)@R(A-) ÷ S(A-)@_R(A-) End-natural in S and R.

Under

reasonable conditions the same observations can be made at the V-level. If we restrict our attention to functors into V with small domains then the functors themselves may be regarded as extra variables. A and B small.

For example,

let T: A°P@A@B + V be a functor with

Then fAT(AAB) is canonically functorial in T and B

for we can write T(AAB) = F(AATB) where F is the composite

A°P@A@([A°P@A@B,V]@B) ~

[A°P@A@B,V]@(A°P@A@B) > V, E

and where E is the evaluation functor defined in [i]

§4.

if S(A-) and R(A-) are functors into V with small domains

Similarly, (and

different variances in A) then S(A-)@__R(A-) is functorial in S and R in a unique way that makes sA: S(A-)@R(A-) ÷ S(A-)@R(A-) natural in S and R. Lastly, let S(A-) be a functor into V which is covariant in A E A.

As part of the data for S, we have a family of morphisms

SAB: A(AB) ÷ [S(A-),S(B-)]

which is natural in A and B and also in

the extra variables in S.

Transforming this family by the

tensor-hom adJunction of V, we get a transformation w-I(SAB):

A(AB)@S(A-) + S(B-) which is natural in A and B and the

extra variables in S.

As a result of the generalised "higher"

representation theorem (see [I], §3 and §5), this induces the Yoneda isomorphism

-12-

YS,B: A(AB)@S(A-)

÷ S(B-).

By Lemma 2.2, we then have Lemma 2.6.

The Yoneda isomorphism YS,A is natural in

A and in the extra variables

in S; if the domain of S is small

then it is natural in S. The following diagram lemmas for the Yoneda isomorphism y are all proved using [3] Proposition as the representatlon

theorem.

in their most convenient Lemma 2.~.

II.7.4 which we shall refer to

These lemmas are presented here

forms for application

in sections

3 and 4.

Given functors S: A ~ V and T: A °p * V

for which SA@_TA exlsts m the following diagram commutes:

(A(AB)O_SA)O3B

> SBe_TB

ZEk

SA@(A(AB)e_TB)

> SAe_TA • icy

Proof.

Replacing @ by @,

we obtain a new diagram:

y by its definition,

etc.,

-13 -

(A(AB) @SA)~TB

\

s@l

\

\ SB@TB

(A(AB) Q_SA)@TB Y@I

\

y~_l ( A(AB)@SA) @_TB

"~ SB@TB

SA@( A( AB )@_TB )

SA@TA

~II

l@y SA@ ( A( AB )@__TB)

SA@(A(AB)@TB)

.

By Lemma

s(s@l)

2.5,

is a coend over A and B hence

to prove that the exterior A, B E A.

SA@TA

This is easily

of this new diagram

it suffices

commutes

seen to be so on applying

the

for all

-14-

representation

theorem;

put B m A and compose both exterior

legs with

(I@SA)@TA

~ (A(AA)@SA)@TA; (JA®I)@I

the resulting diagram commutes, Lemma 2.8.

hence the original one does.

Given functors

S: A°P@B ÷ V and T: B °p ÷ Y

for which S(AC)0_TC exists for each A E A, the followin~ diagram commutes

for each A E A:

A(AB)@(S(BC)®_TC)

S(AC)e_TC

(A(AB)®_S(BC))@_TC , Proof.

Again replacing @ by @,

etc., we obtain a new diagram:

y by its definition,

-15 -

A(AB)~(BC)emc)

A(AB)e(s (BC)_eTc)

~,

~"

S(AC)_OTC ~

A AB )_( aS BC ))_ ~ ((

//

I

S(AC)eTC

~ j~

(A(AB)_eS(BC)~ / / / /

(*(AB)eS(BC))~C In this

diagram the region

transform

labelled

1 commutes b e c a u s e

of t h e d i a g r a m

S(-C)eTC A(AB)

>

[ S(BC)®TC,S(AC)~'C]

!

S(-C)eTC

I [1,s]

[S(BC)e_TC,S(AC)eTC! ~ [ s,1]

[S(BC)®TO,S(AO)®TC]

it

is

the

-16 -

which expresses in A.

the naturality

Hence, because s(l@s)

of s = sC: S(AC)@TC ÷ S(AC)@TC

is a coend over B and C by Lemma

2.5, it suffices to prove that the exterior of the new diagram commutes

for all A, B E A and C E 8.

consequence

of the representation

The remaining

Again this is a simple

theorem.

lemmas are obtained by the same type of

argument. ~

.

for which TCSS(AC) commutes

Given functors S: A°P@B ~ V and T: B °p ~ V exists for each A E A, the following diagram

for each A E A: A(AB)@(TCe_S(BC))

III

~~'TCQS(AC) /

j J

ley

TCO_(A (AB)®_S (BC))

Lemma 2.10.

For any functors S; A ~ 8 and T: B °p ÷ V

the followln~ diagram commutes

for each A E A:

l~y A(AB)@(8(SB,C)®_TC)

> A(AB)%TSB

8(SA,C)~3C

~ TSA Y

-17 -

Lemma 2.11 diasram

commutes

For an~ functor T: A@B + V the following

for all B, D E A:

ley A(AB)@_(B(CD)@_T(AC) )

~

A(AB)@_T(AD)

S(CD )@_T(BC)-

~

T(BD)

.

Y 3.

Premonoidal

We emphaslse all concepts monoidal

over

again that,

are relative

closed category Definition

V consists

a category a functor

Categories unless

otherwise

to the given normallsed

3.1

A premonoidal

category

of

A, P: A°P@A°P@A

÷ V,

isomorphisms

I = AAB: JX@P(XAB)

÷ A(AB),

P = PAB: JX@P(AXB)

~ A(AB),

a = aABCD: satisfying

P(ABX)@P(XCD)

the following

symmetric

V.

a functor J: A * V, and natural

indicated,

÷ P(BCX)@_P(AXD),

two axioms:

P = (A,P,J,A,p,~)

-18 PC1.

For all A,B,C E A, the following diagram commutes: l@a > JXQ_(P(XBY)Q_P(AYC))

JX@_(P(AXY)@_P(YBC) ) -

(JX~P(AXY))~P(YBC)

(JX~_P (XBY)) ~P (AYC)

p@l

A(AY)~_P(YBC)

A(BY)~P(AYC)

P(ABC) PC2.

.

For all A,B,C,D,E E A, the following diagram commutes: P(ABX )0_(P (XCY) ~_P(YDE) )

P(ABX)O(P(CDY)~P(XYE))

(P(ABX)@P(XCY))@P(YDE)

P(CDY)@(P(ABX)@P(XYE))

( P(BCX)~P(AX¥))~_P(YDE)

P(CDY)~(P(BYX)@P(~E))

~II

P (BCX)@( P(AXY) ~_P(YDE) )

P (BCX)@(P(XDY) ~_P(AYE))

(P(CDX)~P(BXY))~P(AYE)

(P(BCX)@P(XDY))@P(AYE)

-19 -

Remark requisite

3.2

It is assumed

~'s exist for the g i v e n

hypothesis

on V, when

P(AB-): A ÷

V and J:

A is small.

in the d e f i n i t i o n

A, P, and J.

|A,V].

to a b l c l o s e d

for all A,B 6 A.

of this s e c t i o n we will suppose

A is small and show that each p r e m o n o i d a l "extends"

They do so, by

They also exist w h e n e v e r

A ÷ V are r e p r e s e n t a b l e

In the r e m a i n d e r

that the

structure

[P,V]

structure

that

P on A

on the functor category

For the m o n o i d a l part define a t e n s o r - p r o d u c t

*: [ A , V ] ~ [ A , V ] (3.1)

÷ [A,V]

by

S*T = fAsA@;BTB@P(AB-)

for all S,T E [A,V];

= SA@(TB@P(AB-))

this e x p r e s s i o n

is c a n o n i c a l l y

in S and T by the c o n s i d e r a t i o n s

of s e c t i o n 2.

J 6 [A,V]

of.,

be the i d e n t l t y - o b J e c t

Isomorphisms respective

£* = ~ :

functorlal

Next,

let

and define n a t u r a l

J*T ÷ T and r* = r~: T.J ÷ J as the

composites

J,T = J X @ ( T A @ P ( X A - ) )

a (JX@P(XA-))@_TA

A(A-)@TA k@l

~ T y

and T.J = T A @ ( J X @ P ( A X - ) )

m (JX@P(AX-))@_TA > T.

A(A-)@_TA p®l Lastly,

define a natural

as the composite

y isomorphism

a* = a~ST:

(R,S),T ÷ R*(S,T)

-

20

-

(R*S)*T = (RA@(SB@P(ABX)))@(TC~P(XC-)) RA@(SB@(TC@(P(ABX)@P(XC-)))) RA@(SB~(TC@(P(BCX)@P(AX-)))) i®(1®(1®~)) RA~((SB@(TC@P(BCX)))@P(AX-)) = R,(S,T). Then £*,

r*, and a* are natural by Lemmas Theorem

monoidal

category admittln5 Proof

category,

[P,V]

3.3

First,

= ([A,VJ,*,J,£*,r*,a*)

to show that [P,V]

is a monoidal

we need to prove PC1 ~ MC2 and PC2 ~ MC3.

commutes by PCI;

definitions

of *,r*,a*,

by the naturality isomorphlsms

diagram

(3.2) in which the

and £*;

4, 5, 6, 7, 8, and 9 commute of the induced coherence

(Lemma 2.5 and the succeeding remarks);

commute by Lemma 2.7; and 12 commutes by Lemma 2.9.

isomorphlsms

The proof

and coherence

of * and a*, uses

of the induced coherence

involved.

To complete the structure on [A,V] biclosed

I0 and Ii

a diagram that is too large for the space

available but, apart from the definitions only the naturality

The first

l, 2, and 3 commute by the

and coherence

of PC2 ~ MC3 requires

is a

a biclosed structure.

of these is obtained by considering exterior

2.5 and 2.6.

category,

consider the composite

to that of a

isomorphism:

®l

r~@l=r~l ~ -

il~

i®(i®y)

10

SX@(TC@P(XCD )

~/(A(AX)~SA)@(TCgP(XCD))4

1

(SA@(JB@P(ABX)))@(TC@P(XCD})

( (JB@_P(ABX))@__SA@ ) _(TC@__P(XCD) )

SAg(TCg(A(AX)~P(XCD)))

®l

v

®i

v

6

SA@(JB@(TC~(P(ABX)@P(XCD))))

SAe(TC@((JB@P(ABX))@P(XCD)))

SA@(TC@(JB@(P(ABX)®P(XCD)) )

/

t -

/

3

l

9

v v

®

F-J

I® I®

SAe(TCe(A(CX)~P(AXD)))

SA@_((A (CX)@_TC)@_P(AXD))

SA@(TX@P(AXD))

i~( ~ *~l )

i

SA@_(((JB@_P(BCX))®_TC)@_P(AXD))

~r SA@((JB~(TC~P(BCX)))@P(AXD))

~Jl

SA@_(JB@_(TC@_(P(BCX)@_P(AXD)))

SA@_(TC@_((JB@P (BCX))@_P(AXD)))

SA@(TC@(JB@(P(BCX)~P(AXD))))

~> SAe(TCeP(ACD))-


P(BCX)@P(AXD)

P(BAX)@P(XCD)

P(ACX)@P(BXD)

P(BCX)@P(XAD)

~

P(CAX)@P(BXD)

.

o@i This definition does not, of course,

require

A to be small. It remains to be shown that [ P,V] admits a symmetric monoidal

closed structure whenever

P has a symmetry.

For this,

define a natural isomorphism c * = C~T: SwT * T~S as the composite

-

S*T

=

24

-

SA@(TB@P(AB-)) ~ TB@(SA®P(AB-)) TB@(SA®P(BA-)) = T*S.

i®(l~c) Again, the naturallty of e* is a consequence of Lemma 2.5. If e is a symmetry for P then c* is a s~etr~

for [P,V]. P~oof

To prove PC3 ~ MC6 consider diagram (3.5): TB~(SA@P(BAC))

TB@(SA@P(ABC))

SA@(TB@_P(BAC))

~

2

(3.5) II~

TB@(SA@P(ABC))

SA~(TB~P(ABC))

u

I@(I~o)

SA~(TB~P(ABC))

Region 1 commutes by PC3, and region 2 commutes by the naturallty of the Induoed coherence isomorphism involved; hence the exterior commutes and so, by definition of c*, Me6 is satisfied.

To prove

PC4 ~ MC7 consider diagram (3.6), in which the exterior commutes by PC4; i, 2, and 3 commute by the definitions of , and c*; 4, 5, and 6 commute by the definition of a*; and 7, 8, 9, and i0 commute by the naturality and coherence of induced coherence Isomorphlsms.

.i-

/

a •

SBO_((TC~_(~A03 (ACX)) ) ~_P(BXD))

Imc m

aM

le(1®(1~))

c**l

SB@_((RAQ_(TC~P(ACX)) )~_P(BXD))

RA@(SB@(TC~(P(ACX)~P(BXD))))

®I

v

I

(SB@(RA@P(BAX)))@(TC@P(XCD))

(l@(l@~))@_l I

(RA~(SB@P(ABX)))~(TC@P(XCD))

RA@(SB@(TC@(P(BAX)@__P(XCD))))

®I

,-4

®I

®I

v

®I ~D

(SB~(RA~P(ABX)))@(TC~P(XCD))

RA@(SB~(TC~(P(ABX)~P(XCD))))

I

!~