Lecture 16 From Kant to Aristotle
Plan for today
I
Kant: Review and critique
Plan for today
I I
Kant: Review and critique Aristotle: wellbeing and the good
Kant - Review and critique
Review
I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional
Review
I I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional So, Kant derives morality from a categorical imperative.
Review
I I I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional So, Kant derives morality from a categorical imperative. It has several formulations, including these:
Review
I I I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional So, Kant derives morality from a categorical imperative. It has several formulations, including these: I
The Formula of the Universal Law (FUL)
Review
I I I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional So, Kant derives morality from a categorical imperative. It has several formulations, including these: I
The Formula of the Universal Law (FUL) I
Act in such a way that you could will the principle of your action to be universal law.
Review
I I I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional So, Kant derives morality from a categorical imperative. It has several formulations, including these: I
The Formula of the Universal Law (FUL) I
I
Act in such a way that you could will the principle of your action to be universal law.
The Formula of the End in Itself (FEI)
Review
I I I
Morality is a source of requirements which are unconditional So, Kant derives morality from a categorical imperative. It has several formulations, including these: I
The Formula of the Universal Law (FUL) I
I
Act in such a way that you could will the principle of your action to be universal law.
The Formula of the End in Itself (FEI) I
Treat the humanity in people never merely as a means, but always as an end.
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction?
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction? I
a means is something done for the sake of an end
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction? I
a means is something done for the sake of an end I
the end makes the means worth doing
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction? I
a means is something done for the sake of an end I I
the end makes the means worth doing thus the means derives value from the end
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction? I
a means is something done for the sake of an end I I
I
the end makes the means worth doing thus the means derives value from the end
How does the means/end distinction figure in the FEI?
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction? I
a means is something done for the sake of an end I I
I
the end makes the means worth doing thus the means derives value from the end
How does the means/end distinction figure in the FEI? I
a mere means is something whose value derives entirely from something else
Clarifying the FEI, 1
I
What is this means/end distinction? I
a means is something done for the sake of an end I I
I
the end makes the means worth doing thus the means derives value from the end
How does the means/end distinction figure in the FEI? I
I
a mere means is something whose value derives entirely from something else an end-in-itself is something whose value derives not at all from anything else
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts:
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1:
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value So, when you do A for the sake of B, and B for the sake of C, etc., this chain comes to an end with a source of intrinsic value, and that end is humanity
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I I
I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value So, when you do A for the sake of B, and B for the sake of C, etc., this chain comes to an end with a source of intrinsic value, and that end is humanity
Regarding 2:
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I I
I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value So, when you do A for the sake of B, and B for the sake of C, etc., this chain comes to an end with a source of intrinsic value, and that end is humanity
Regarding 2: I
To treat someone as a mere means is to regard their value as instrumental
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I I
I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value So, when you do A for the sake of B, and B for the sake of C, etc., this chain comes to an end with a source of intrinsic value, and that end is humanity
Regarding 2: I
I
To treat someone as a mere means is to regard their value as instrumental for example, to use them
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I I
I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value So, when you do A for the sake of B, and B for the sake of C, etc., this chain comes to an end with a source of intrinsic value, and that end is humanity
Regarding 2: I
I
To treat someone as a mere means is to regard their value as instrumental for example, to use them I
to subordinate their interests to another project
Clarifying the FEI, 2 I
The formula has two parts: 1. do treat humanity as an end in itself, and 2. do not treat humanity as mere means
I
Regarding 1: I I
I
Humanity is the source of intrinsic value So, when you do A for the sake of B, and B for the sake of C, etc., this chain comes to an end with a source of intrinsic value, and that end is humanity
Regarding 2: I
I
To treat someone as a mere means is to regard their value as instrumental for example, to use them I I
to subordinate their interests to another project even if that other project has its merits
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem”
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down.
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it?
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Most people say that it is wrong to intervene in case 2, but many hesitate about case 1.
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Most people say that it is wrong to intervene in case 2, but many hesitate about case 1. I
What explains the difference?
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Most people say that it is wrong to intervene in case 2, but many hesitate about case 1. I I
What explains the difference? One hypothesis:
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Most people say that it is wrong to intervene in case 2, but many hesitate about case 1. I I
What explains the difference? One hypothesis: I
in case 2, you are killing the bystander in order to save other people,
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Most people say that it is wrong to intervene in case 2, but many hesitate about case 1. I I
What explains the difference? One hypothesis: I
I
in case 2, you are killing the bystander in order to save other people, whereas in case 1, the death of the bystander is a consequence, rather than an instrument, of the action
Applying the FEI I
Consider the notorious “Trolley Problem” I
I
I
I
A trolley is hurtling out of control down the track. At the end of the track are five people tied down. In case 1, you can flip a switch, diverting the trolley onto another track where it will hit just a single person. Would you do it? In case 2, you can push a bystander onto the track, stopping the trolley but killing that person
Most people say that it is wrong to intervene in case 2, but many hesitate about case 1. I I
What explains the difference? One hypothesis: I
I
I
in case 2, you are killing the bystander in order to save other people, whereas in case 1, the death of the bystander is a consequence, rather than an instrument, of the action
Intervention in case 2 is clearly forbidden by the FEI
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws I
e.g., lying is absolutely forbidden under all circumstances
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
e.g., lying is absolutely forbidden under all circumstances
Can’t you imagine a circumstance in which lying is obligatory?
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
e.g., lying is absolutely forbidden under all circumstances
Can’t you imagine a circumstance in which lying is obligatory? I
If so then we have two options:
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
e.g., lying is absolutely forbidden under all circumstances
Can’t you imagine a circumstance in which lying is obligatory? I
If so then we have two options: I
either sometimes lying is not forbidden,
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
e.g., lying is absolutely forbidden under all circumstances
Can’t you imagine a circumstance in which lying is obligatory? I
If so then we have two options: I I
either sometimes lying is not forbidden, or there are actions you are both required and forbidden to do.
Critique 1
I
Kant holds that morality is a system of absolute and unconditional laws I
I
General laws, like UL and FEI, entail particular laws I
I
This is because morality is founded on reason alone
e.g., lying is absolutely forbidden under all circumstances
Can’t you imagine a circumstance in which lying is obligatory? I
If so then we have two options: I I
I
either sometimes lying is not forbidden, or there are actions you are both required and forbidden to do.
either way, it is now hard to accept that morality is founded on reason alone
Critique 2 I
According to Kant,
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I
emotions have no moral significance, and
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
For example, suppose that Linus is naturally generous and sympathetic, and Minus is naturally stingy and unsympathetic.
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
I I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
For example, suppose that Linus is naturally generous and sympathetic, and Minus is naturally stingy and unsympathetic. Each has an acquaintance who is stranded at 3am on a country road
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
I I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
For example, suppose that Linus is naturally generous and sympathetic, and Minus is naturally stingy and unsympathetic. Each has an acquaintance who is stranded at 3am on a country road I
Linus gets pleasure out of situations like this, and so leaps out of bed
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
I I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
For example, suppose that Linus is naturally generous and sympathetic, and Minus is naturally stingy and unsympathetic. Each has an acquaintance who is stranded at 3am on a country road I
I
Linus gets pleasure out of situations like this, and so leaps out of bed Minus would prefer to keep to himself, but reasons that if he were stranded, he’d want help too, and so decides that he has to help
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
I I
For example, suppose that Linus is naturally generous and sympathetic, and Minus is naturally stingy and unsympathetic. Each has an acquaintance who is stranded at 3am on a country road I
I
I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
Linus gets pleasure out of situations like this, and so leaps out of bed Minus would prefer to keep to himself, but reasons that if he were stranded, he’d want help too, and so decides that he has to help
Kant says that since Linus is getting pleasure anyway, only Minus’s action is morally praiseworthy
Critique 2 I
According to Kant, I I
I I
For example, suppose that Linus is naturally generous and sympathetic, and Minus is naturally stingy and unsympathetic. Each has an acquaintance who is stranded at 3am on a country road I
I
I I
emotions have no moral significance, and nor does character
Linus gets pleasure out of situations like this, and so leaps out of bed Minus would prefer to keep to himself, but reasons that if he were stranded, he’d want help too, and so decides that he has to help
Kant says that since Linus is getting pleasure anyway, only Minus’s action is morally praiseworthy But is this right?
Goodbye Kant
Hello Aristotle
Plan for Aristotle’s ethics
1. Happiness as the good
Plan for Aristotle’s ethics
1. Happiness as the good 2. Virtues and pleasure
Plan for Aristotle’s ethics
1. Happiness as the good 2. Virtues and pleasure 3. Friendship and contemplation
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens developed the first broadly systematic European philosophy; his works ranged over
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens developed the first broadly systematic European philosophy; his works ranged over I
anatomy, astronomy, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology;
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens developed the first broadly systematic European philosophy; his works ranged over I
I
anatomy, astronomy, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology; aesthetics, economics, ethics, logic, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology;
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens developed the first broadly systematic European philosophy; his works ranged over I
I
I
anatomy, astronomy, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology; aesthetics, economics, ethics, logic, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology; education, anthropology, literature and poetry.
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens developed the first broadly systematic European philosophy; his works ranged over I
I
I I
anatomy, astronomy, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology; aesthetics, economics, ethics, logic, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology; education, anthropology, literature and poetry.
we have records of his work only through lecture notes
Bio-capsule I
Aristotle (384–322 BC) was born in Macedonia I I I I
joined Plato’s academy in Athens at age 18 served as tutor to Alexander the Great for most of his adult life wrote the constitution of Athens developed the first broadly systematic European philosophy; his works ranged over I
I
I I I
anatomy, astronomy, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology; aesthetics, economics, ethics, logic, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology; education, anthropology, literature and poetry.
we have records of his work only through lecture notes throughout the middle ages the phrase “the philosopher” referred to Aristotle
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
the basic ethical question is: what is human wellbeing?
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
the basic ethical question is: what is human wellbeing? I
wellbeing = happiness = “eudaimonia”
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
the basic ethical question is: what is human wellbeing? I I
wellbeing = happiness = “eudaimonia” wellbeing is virtuous action over the course of a whole life
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
I
the basic ethical question is: what is human wellbeing? I I
I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
wellbeing = happiness = “eudaimonia” wellbeing is virtuous action over the course of a whole life
you make progress in the study of ethics by coming to understand how the different aspects of a good character work together in a well-lived life
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
I
the basic ethical question is: what is human wellbeing? I I
I
I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
wellbeing = happiness = “eudaimonia” wellbeing is virtuous action over the course of a whole life
you make progress in the study of ethics by coming to understand how the different aspects of a good character work together in a well-lived life this requires a good upbringing, plus patience and experience, plus good fortune
Aristotle’s ethics: an overview I I
For Aristotle, the point of the study of ethics is to improve our lives So, ethics is not a theoretical science I
I
the basic ethical question is: what is human wellbeing? I I
I
I I
it does not involve any special technical knowledge
wellbeing = happiness = “eudaimonia” wellbeing is virtuous action over the course of a whole life
you make progress in the study of ethics by coming to understand how the different aspects of a good character work together in a well-lived life this requires a good upbringing, plus patience and experience, plus good fortune it is not based on rules, and can’t be learned by powerpoint
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity.
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end I
e.g., the archer aims to strike the target
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end I
I
e.g., the archer aims to strike the target
if each end were desired only for the sake of some further end, then the process would go to infinity, and our desires would be empty and vain
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end I
I
I
e.g., the archer aims to strike the target
if each end were desired only for the sake of some further end, then the process would go to infinity, and our desires would be empty and vain so, something must be desired for its own sake
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end I
I
I I
e.g., the archer aims to strike the target
if each end were desired only for the sake of some further end, then the process would go to infinity, and our desires would be empty and vain so, something must be desired for its own sake this one thing, desired for its own sake, is the good
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end I
I
I I
I
e.g., the archer aims to strike the target
if each end were desired only for the sake of some further end, then the process would go to infinity, and our desires would be empty and vain so, something must be desired for its own sake this one thing, desired for its own sake, is the good
Isn’t this argument fallacious?
The unity of the good, 1
I
Aristotle argues (p545) that there is something, the good, which is the single aim of all activity. I
every action aims at some end I
I
I I
I
e.g., the archer aims to strike the target
if each end were desired only for the sake of some further end, then the process would go to infinity, and our desires would be empty and vain so, something must be desired for its own sake this one thing, desired for its own sake, is the good
Isn’t this argument fallacious? I
e.g., couldn’t there be many things desired for their own sake?
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product,
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it.
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it. e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I want dough”
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I I
I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it. e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I want dough”
but for Aristotle, an end is usually a broader activity
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I I
I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it. e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I want dough”
but for Aristotle, an end is usually a broader activity I
e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I am baking”
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I I
I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it. e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I want dough”
but for Aristotle, an end is usually a broader activity I I
e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I am baking” “why am I baking?–because I am feeding my family”, etc.
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I I
I
but for Aristotle, an end is usually a broader activity I I
I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it. e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I want dough”
e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I am baking” “why am I baking?–because I am feeding my family”, etc.
if you think that ends are products, then it is hard to see why the good should be a single thing
The unity of the good, 2
I
later philosophers think that an end is a product, I I
I
but for Aristotle, an end is usually a broader activity I I
I I
you desire a product, and so act to produce it. e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I want dough”
e.g., “Why am I moistening the flour?—because I am baking” “why am I baking?–because I am feeding my family”, etc.
if you think that ends are products, then it is hard to see why the good should be a single thing but if you think that ends are broader activities, then it is natural to suppose that the ends of all activities eventually converge
what are we doing when we do ethics? I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science I
its object is not knowledge or truth, but understanding of the good
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science I
I
its object is not knowledge or truth, but understanding of the good
cautionary note: every subject matter requires a degree of precision appropriate to it
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science I
I
its object is not knowledge or truth, but understanding of the good
cautionary note: every subject matter requires a degree of precision appropriate to it I
mathematics requires extreme precision
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science I
I
its object is not knowledge or truth, but understanding of the good
cautionary note: every subject matter requires a degree of precision appropriate to it I I
mathematics requires extreme precision physics somewhat less
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science I
I
its object is not knowledge or truth, but understanding of the good
cautionary note: every subject matter requires a degree of precision appropriate to it I I I
mathematics requires extreme precision physics somewhat less biology gets messy
what are we doing when we do ethics? I I I
if there is a single ultimate aim of action, then knowing about it would be useful the particular aim of ethics is the wisdom of understanding the single aim of all action so ethics not a theoretical science I
I
its object is not knowledge or truth, but understanding of the good
cautionary note: every subject matter requires a degree of precision appropriate to it I I I I
mathematics requires extreme precision physics somewhat less biology gets messy in ethics, there are only rules of thumb
Wellbeing as the good
I
According to most people, the good is wellbeing
Wellbeing as the good
I I
According to most people, the good is wellbeing But they disagree about what wellbeing is
Wellbeing as the good
I I
According to most people, the good is wellbeing But they disagree about what wellbeing is I
Pleasure?
Wellbeing as the good
I I
According to most people, the good is wellbeing But they disagree about what wellbeing is I I
Pleasure? Honor?
Wellbeing as the good
I I
According to most people, the good is wellbeing But they disagree about what wellbeing is I I I
Pleasure? Honor? The contemplative life?
Wellbeing as the good
I I
According to most people, the good is wellbeing But they disagree about what wellbeing is I I I
I
Pleasure? Honor? The contemplative life?
Aristotle will develop this commonsensical view
Objection
I
Recall Kant’s objection to the idea of wellbeing as the highest good
Objection
I
Recall Kant’s objection to the idea of wellbeing as the highest good I
Some happy people are a–holes
Objection
I
Recall Kant’s objection to the idea of wellbeing as the highest good I
I
Some happy people are a–holes
However: Aristotle will develop a conception of wellbeing (eudaimonia) which resists this objection
Objection
I
Recall Kant’s objection to the idea of wellbeing as the highest good I
I
Some happy people are a–holes
However: Aristotle will develop a conception of wellbeing (eudaimonia) which resists this objection I
For Aristotle, wellbeing is incompatible with being an a–hole
Next time
I
function of man
Next time
I I
function of man nature of wellbeing
Next time
I I I
function of man nature of wellbeing virtue and pleasure